Operator Variables in Logical Graphs • 1

In lieu of a field study requirement for my bachelor’s degree I spent two years in various state and university libraries reading everything I could find by and about Peirce, poring most memorably through reels of microfilmed Peirce manuscripts Michigan State had at the time, all in trying to track down some hint of a clue to a puzzling passage in Peirce’s “Simplest Mathematics”, most acutely coming to a head with that bizarre line of type at CP 4.306, which the editors of Peirce’s Collected Papers, no doubt compromised by the typographer’s reluctance to cut new symbols, transmogrified into a script more cryptic than even the manuscript’s original hieroglyphic.

I found one key to the mystery in Peirce’s use of operator variables, which he and his students Christine Ladd‑Franklin and O.H. Mitchell explored in depth.  I will shortly discuss that theme as it affects logical graphs but it may be useful to give a shorter and sweeter explanation of how the basic idea typically arises in common logical practice.

Consider De Morgan’s rules:

\begin{array}{lll}  \lnot (A \land B) & = & \lnot A \lor \lnot B  \\[6px]  \lnot (A \lor B) & = & \lnot A \land \lnot B  \end{array}

The common form exhibited by the two rules could be captured in a single formula by taking ``o_1" and ``o_2" as variable names ranging over a family of logical operators, then asking what substitutions for o_1 and o_2 would satisfy the following equation.

\begin{array}{lll}  \lnot (A ~o_1~ B) & = & \lnot A ~o_2~ \lnot B  \end{array}

We already know two solutions to this operator equation, namely, (o_1, o_2) = (\land, \lor) and (o_1, o_2) = (\lor, \land).  Wouldn’t it be just like Peirce to ask if there are others?

Having broached the subject of logical operator variables, I will leave it for now in the same way Peirce himself did:

I shall not further enlarge upon this matter at this point, although the conception mentioned opens a wide field;  because it cannot be set in its proper light without overstepping the limits of dichotomic mathematics.  (Collected Papers, CP 4.306).

Further exploration of operator variables and operator invariants treads on grounds traditionally known as second intentional logic and “opens a wide field”, as Peirce says.  For now, however, I will tend to that corner of the field where our garden variety logical graphs grow, observing the ways in which operative variations and operative themes naturally develop on those grounds.

cc: FB | Logical GraphsLaws of FormMathstodonAcademia.edu
cc: Conceptual GraphsCyberneticsStructural ModelingSystems Science

This entry was posted in Amphecks, Animata, Boolean Algebra, Boolean Functions, C.S. Peirce, Cactus Graphs, Constraint Satisfaction Problems, Deduction, Diagrammatic Reasoning, Duality, Equational Inference, Graph Theory, Laws of Form, Logic, Logical Graphs, Mathematics, Minimal Negation Operators, Model Theory, Painted Cacti, Peirce, Proof Theory, Propositional Calculus, Propositional Equation Reasoning Systems, Spencer Brown, Theorem Proving, Visualization and tagged , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , , . Bookmark the permalink.

3 Responses to Operator Variables in Logical Graphs • 1

  1. Pingback: Survey of Animated Logical Graphs • 7 | Inquiry Into Inquiry

  2. Pingback: Operator Variables in Logical Graphs • Discussion 1 | Inquiry Into Inquiry

  3. Pingback: Operator Variables in Logical Graphs • Discussion 2 | Inquiry Into Inquiry

Leave a comment

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.