Peirce’s 1870 “Logic of Relatives” • Comment 11.16
We now have enough material on morphisms to go back and cast a more studied eye on what Peirce is doing with that “number of” function, whose application to a logical term is indicated by writing the term in square brackets, as
It is convenient to have a prefix notation for the function mapping a term
to a number
but Peirce previously reserved the letter
for logical
so let’s use
as a variant for
My plan will be nothing less plodding than to work through the statements Peirce made in defining and explaining the “number of” function up to our present place in the paper, namely, the budget of points collected in Comment 11.2.
NOF 1
I propose to assign to all logical terms, numbers; to an absolute term, the number of individuals it denotes; to a relative term, the average number of things so related to one individual. Thus in a universe of perfect men (men), the number of “tooth of” would be The number of a relative with two correlates would be the average number of things so related to a pair of individuals; and so on for relatives of higher numbers of correlates. I propose to denote the number of a logical term by enclosing the term in square brackets, thus
The role of the “number of” function may be formalized by assigning it a name and a type, in the present discussion where
is a suitable set of signs, a syntactic domain, containing all the logical terms whose numbers we need to evaluate in a given context, and where
is the set of real numbers.
Transcribing Peirce’s example:
To spell it out in words, the number of the relative term in a universe of perfect human dentition is equal to the number of teeth of humans divided by the number of humans, that is,
The dyadic relative term determines a dyadic relation
where
and
contain all the teeth and all the people, respectively, under discussion.
A rough indication of the bigraph for might be drawn as follows, showing just the first few items in the toothy part of
and the peoply part of
Notice that the “number of” function needs the data represented by the entire bigraph for
in order to compute the value
Finally, one observes this component of is a function in the direction
since we are counting only teeth which occupy exactly one mouth of a tooth-bearing creature.
Resources
- Peirce’s 1870 Logic of Relatives • Part 1 • Part 2 • Part 3 • References
- Logic Syllabus • Relational Concepts • Relation Theory • Relative Term
cc: Cybernetics • Ontolog Forum • Structural Modeling • Systems Science
cc: FB | Peirce Matters • Laws of Form • Peirce List (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7)
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 3 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Peirce’s 1870 “Logic Of Relatives” • Overview | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Peirce’s 1870 “Logic Of Relatives” • Comment 1 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 4 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 5 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 6 | Inquiry Into Inquiry