Peirce’s 1870 “Logic of Relatives” • Comment 11.20
We come to the last of Peirce’s statements about the “number of” function, first quoted in Selection 11 and again with the whole set in Comment 11.2.
NOF 4.1
The conception of multiplication we have adopted is that of the application of one relation to another. […]
Even ordinary numerical multiplication involves the same idea, for is a pair of triplets, and
is a triplet of pairs, where “triplet of” and “pair of” are evidently relatives.
If we have an equation of the form
and there are just as many x’s per y as there are, per things, things of the universe, then we have also the arithmetical equation,
(Peirce, CP 3.76)
Peirce here observes what may be called a contingent morphism. On a condition he gives, the mapping of logical terms to their corresponding numbers preserves the multiplication of relative terms after the fashion of the following formula.
Equivalently:
The condition for this to hold is expressed by Peirce in the following manner.
There are just as many x’s per y as there are, per things, things of the universe.
Peirce’s phrasing on this point is admittedly hard to parse but if we stick with his story to the end I think we can see what he’s driving at.
NOF 4.2
For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then
holds arithmetically. (Peirce, CP 3.76).
Now that is something we can sink our teeth into and trace the bigraph representation of the situation. It will help to recall our first examination of the “tooth of” relation and to adjust the picture we sketched of it on that occasion.
Transcribing Peirce’s example:
That is to say, the number of the relative term “tooth of” is equal to the number of teeth of humans divided by the number of humans. In a universe of perfect human dentition this gives a quotient of 32.
The dyadic relative term determines a dyadic relation
where
contains all the teeth and
contains all the people under discussion.
To make the case as simple as possible and still cover the point, suppose there are just four people in our universe of discourse and just two of them are French. The bigraph product below shows the pertinent facts of the case.
In this picture the order of relational composition flows down the page. For convenience in composing relations, the absolute term is inflected by the comma functor to form the dyadic relative term
which in turn determines the idempotent representation of Frenchmen as a subset of mankind,
By way of a legend for the Figure, we have the following data.
We can use this picture to make sense of Peirce’s statement, repeated below.
NOF 4.2
For instance, if our universe is perfect men, and there are as many teeth to a Frenchman (perfect understood) as there are to any one of the universe, then
holds arithmetically. (Peirce, CP 3.76)
In statistical terms, Peirce is saying this: If the population of Frenchmen is a fair sample of the general population with regard to the factor of dentition, then the morphic equation,
whose transpose gives the equation,
is every bit as true as the defining equation in this circumstance, namely,
Resources
- Peirce’s 1870 Logic of Relatives • Part 1 • Part 2 • Part 3 • References
- Logic Syllabus • Relational Concepts • Relation Theory • Relative Term
cc: Cybernetics • Ontolog Forum • Structural Modeling • Systems Science
cc: FB | Peirce Matters • Laws of Form (1) (2) • Peirce List (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7)
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 3 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Peirce’s 1870 “Logic Of Relatives” • Overview | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Peirce’s 1870 “Logic Of Relatives” • Comment 1 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 4 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 5 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 6 | Inquiry Into Inquiry