Peirce’s 1870 “Logic of Relatives” • Comment 11.9
Among the variety of regularities affecting dyadic relations we pay special attention to the -regularity conditions where
is equal to
Let be an arbitrary dyadic relation. The following properties can be defined.
We previously examined dyadic relations exemplifying each of these regularity conditions. Then we introduced a few bits of terminology and special-purpose notations for working with tubular relations.
We arrive by way of this winding stair at the special cases of dyadic relations variously described as
-regular, total and tubular, or total prefunctions on specified domains,
or
or both, and which are more often celebrated as functions on those domains.
If is a pre-function
that happens to be total at
then
is known as a function from
to
typically indicated as
To say that a relation is total and tubular at
is to say that
is
-regular at
Thus, we may formalize the following definitions.
For example, let and let
be the dyadic relation depicted in the bigraph below.
We observe that is a function at
and we record this fact in either of the manners
or
Resources
- Peirce’s 1870 Logic of Relatives • Part 1 • Part 2 • Part 3 • References
- Logic Syllabus • Relational Concepts • Relation Theory • Relative Term
cc: Cybernetics • Ontolog Forum • Structural Modeling • Systems Science
cc: FB | Peirce Matters • Laws of Form • Peirce List (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7)
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 3 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Peirce’s 1870 “Logic Of Relatives” • Overview | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Peirce’s 1870 “Logic Of Relatives” • Comment 1 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 4 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 5 | Inquiry Into Inquiry
Pingback: Survey of Relation Theory • 6 | Inquiry Into Inquiry